THE PRINCIPLES OF VALID INFERENCE
(APPLIED IN SYLLOGISTIC LOGIC)

Inference, or reasoning logically, is the deriving of one truth from others. This means that a 'new' proposition (or statement) is accepted as true because the proposition is a valid conclusion from propositions themselves accepted as true. 'Valid refers to 'self-consistency' and is applied to the logical form of an argument, not to its material contents. The distinction between 'form' and 'content' is essential to all logical reasoning, one which will be made evident by examples in the following.
The principles of valid inference are fundamental and essential 'laws of thought' or 'axioms' which underlie all valid reasoning. They are not established by experience, being analytical statements and thus being self-evident.


The three main principles were formulated by Aristotle. A fourth principle given below, Leibnitz' principle, is connected with experience and thus concerns material reasoning rather than formal logic.

The Principle of Identity (A is A) stated briefly, means that the same term must always have the same meaning. The concept of Identity implies the concept of Diversity, because A is A is only significant because we refer to possible diversity.

The Principle of Contradiction (A cannot both be B and not-B) means that of two contradictory assertions about the same subject, both cannot be true - i.e. one must be false. In other words, incompatible propositions cannot be true together. This principle has previously been considered under the more accurate or fitting title 'Principle of Non-Contradiction' . However, since the other less explanatory usage is engrained, it is in this part of the book named that accordingly. This principle is derived from that of identity above.
Its application:-
(a) to the meaning of terms:- it secures the identical meaning of a term by denying a term to be diverted to another meaning in the same discourse.
b) to the mutual consistency of propositions: incompatible propositions can not be true together.

The Principle of Excluded Middle (A either is, or is not, B) denies that there can be any Intermediate alternative between truth and falsity. Hence it refers to contradictories - and not contraries. (Known traditionally as 'tertium non datur' or 'no third possibility exists').

Its application:-
(a) to the meaning of a term:- any given meaning of a term either does, or does not, belong to a given term in a given context.
(b) to the mutual consistency of propositions:- of relations between classes and another limitation, namely that it only deals with relations of identity and difference (or relations reducible to these) seems due to the unnatural classification of propositions of the traditional doctrine. In the first case the singular-termed proposition was forced to be considered universal and, secondly, the only recognised relationship between terms was the subject-attribute relation.

General Rules of The Syllogism. (Relating to "structure")
I A syllogism must have three, and only three, terms
II A syllogism must have three, and only three, propositions (relating to "quantity")
III The middle term must be distributed in at least one premise
IV No term may be distributed in the conclusion that is not distributed in its premise (relating to "quality".
V At least one of the premises must be affirmative - (i.e. no conclusion can follow from two negative premises)
VI A negative premise necessitates a negative conclusion, and a negative conclusion must be preceded by a negative premise.

Corolloraries
VII Two particular premises give no valid conclusion
VIII A particular premise necessitates a particular conclusion
IX From a particular major and a negative minor nothing can be inferred.
The general rules of the syllogism are distinguished from the 'special rules', which exist for each separate figure. The special rules depend on the general rules, which in turn depend on the Laws or Principles of Thought (i.e. Axioms of Reasoning). In the widest sense though, all are interdependent.

A general description of the requirement for a valid inference may be:-
A valid inference is the drawing of a conclusion that follows with logical necessity from any two premises. (See also in the following under 'valid conclusion' etc.)
(Note. The principles of logic are largely only illustrated here. For an exhaustive statement of principles and derived logical rules, a fuller study in logic should be sought.)

Strictly speaking, an inference cannot be invalid for it is then not genuinely an inference. There occur apparently-valid inferences which, on closer analysis, are seen not to follow with logical stringency from the premises. These will be referred to hereafter as Invalid arguments or invalid deductions. Deduction is the process of drawing a conclusion from premises, whether by valid or invalid inference. A 'premise' is always a categorical statement, but can be either particular or general. It constitutes one of the grounds or reasons for the conclusion. At least one premise in an argument will usually be general (called 'the major premise') if the conclusion is to be valid in most types of argument. 'Logical necessity' means 'strict dependence upon clear and consistent reasoning'. The description states a general rule of valid deduction, which is specified by various sets of logical rules. Such rules are developed with the stringency of mathematical reasoning. Different sets of rules apply to different basic types of argument. In the following the most common type of argument structure will mostly be considered, those of 'class entailment', whereby the relations of inclusion and exclusion between any two classes (of particulars) are examined systematically.

Deductive reasoning is of an overall hypothetical structure 'If a and b, then c'. The symbols 'a' and 'b' below stand for categorical statements.

Example of a 'class entailment' argument (or 'traditional syllogism')
(a) If all humans are mortals (Major premise - general, categorical statement)
(b) and if the Pope is human (Minor premise - particular categorical statement)
(c) then the Pope is mortal. (Conclusion - particular categorical statement)
Here, an individual (the Pope) is included under the classes of humans and mortals. The class 'humans' entails the class 'mortals' which in turn entails all individuals, such as the Pope. The term 'entails' can thus be interpreted as 'includes under' a class.

Ad 'logical form' and 'material content' of propositions
;

Example:-
Suppose we 'abstract' the 'logical form' - from the 'material content':-Let 3 = logical subject of the conclusion, P = the logical predicate of the conclusion and. M as the 'middle term' which is common to both premises. We get:-

(a) If all M = P (Major premise) where El stands for the class 'all humans'
(b) and S = M (Minor premise) and P for the class 'mortal'
(c) then S = P (Conclusion Valid) and S for the individual 'the Pope'.

This logical structure is known as a 'syllogism'. It is a valid structure in this case, for it is logically necessary that, if the major and minor premises are both true, the conclusion is also necessarily true. Whatever definite classes or individuals are substituted for S, P and M, the conclusion will always follow logically from the premises.

This is illustrated by Venn's diagram as follows:-

The class M is wholly included by the class P (P entails M). The individual S is wholly included by the class M (S is entailed by M). Therefore the individual S is wholly included by the class P also of necessity. (S is also entailed by P). Note that in the concrete example, M does not entail P, though P does entail M (i.e. there are other mortal beings than humans, such as animals). In other words M and P are not mutually entailed. M is thus represented within P.


Consider the following argument:
(a) If all nuclear tests lead to radioactive pollution of the environment
(b) and some radioactive pollution of the environment leads to incurable illnesses
(c) then some nuclear tests lead to incurable illnesses.

Abstracted we get:

Where M = 'lead to radioactive pollution of the environment'
and S = 'nuclear tests' and P = 'lead to incurable illnesses',
we get:-
(a) If all S = M and
(b) and some M = P
(c) then some S = P
With Venn's
diagrams we
see either
 or

Since all S are included by M, but only some of M is included by P, it is possible for all of S to fall within M while falling outside P. Therefore the conclusion is not necessarily true as a result of the truth of the premises. This syllogistic structure is invalid, therefore. The truth of the conclusion cannot however be excluded, for some S might be included under P, but it is not logically entailed by P.

Consider also the example;
(a) If no bachelors are bigamists (True)
(b) and all men are bigamists (False)
(c) then no bachelors are men (False)
The structure of the above is:-

Where S = bachelors, M =bigamists and P = men, we get:-
(a) If no S = M
(b) and all P = M
(c) then no S = P
With Venn's
diagrams we
see
 but not


because all P must be included under M. As the diagram on the left makes clear, the logical structure is valid, the conclusion follows from the premises with necessity even though the conclusion is false.

From this analysis we can see to that if a logical structure that is valid has one true and one false premise, the conclusion will sometimes be true, sometimes be false. No logical necessity is involved here.
Even when both premises are false it is possible for a true conclusion to be arrived at with a valid syllogism;-

(a) If no cats are mammals (False)
(b) & all mammals are dogs false)
(c) then no cats are dogs. (True and valid)
This means that one can sometimes arrive at a true statement on the basis of false evidence, even by logical necessity. The premises in any syllogism always have to be established independently by observation (or by reasoning validly from true observation).

Another example of a valid syllogistic structure, this tine using the (quantifier 'some' in one of the premises:-
(a) If no S = M
(b) and some P = U
(c) then some P = not-S To give a concrete example:- (a) If no gipsies are blue-eyed
(b) and some travelling people are blue-eyed
(c) then some travelling people are not-gipsies.

Provided that it is true that there are no blue-eyed gipsies, and some travelling people are blue-eyed, it must be true that some travelling people are not gipsies. We cannot know from this however, whether the conclusion is true or false until we know that both the premises are true.

The foregoing gives a basis for defining the distinction between validity and truth. A valid conclusion is one the correctness of which follows with logical necessity from other statements. (i.e. a logical conclusion from premises, or a valid analytic statement).

A true statement is a synthetic statement which is verifiable by observation. Similarly, an invalid conclusion's incorrectness follows with logical necessity from some other statements.(i.e.- from premises or definitions. An invalid analytic statement would thus be an invalid conclusion from a definition or a rule of language usage).

False statements are synthetic statements which are falsifiable by observation (such as untruths, lies or erroneous statements of fact). Further, there are unverifiable statements, being those which cannot be tested by some form of observation, even though they are synthetic and thus can be either true or false.


Other types of logical argumentation

The proceeding gives a general outline of various central concepts and methods in that area of logic known as syllogistic logic, which is logic in its traditional meaning, being largely identical with Aristotle's logic logic (developed into so-called 'traditional logic'). An equally fundamental area of logic is usually known as 'prepositional logic' or 'prepositional calculus'. This represents a special formal language in which propositions are expressed so as to exhibit their logical form - as distinct from their logical content - in a yet more abbreviated manner than here employed. The purpose of prepositional logic is to provide clear standards of meaning and validity of inference according to which sentences (with content) can be translated into formal propositions (with form only) for evaluation as to their truth value. For example, the conjunctive terms 'and', 'or', 'not', 'if and 'then' are formalised, which is to say that their use is fixed by logical convention for the purposes of overview of their logical meaning when they occur in complex series of reasoning. Part of prepositional logic is made up of what Aristotle analysed as hypothetical, disjunctive and alternative arguments.

At a more general level of logical theory, quantification theory arises. This theory forms a general basis for both prepositional and syllogistic logic. It widens the scope of syllogistic logic by allowing the analysis of arguments with class quantifiers other than the three basic quantifiers permissible in syllogistic logic (i.e. All, none and Some)

At a yet more general or embracing level are the logical theories of identity and quantity.



EXERCISES (VALID INFERENCE)

1) What can be validly deduced from the following two premises, if anything?
(a) If every U.S. President was a male
(b) and a movie actor was U.S. President
(c) then…
Explain why you consider your conclusion valid or invalid.


2) If indiscriminate spending is a proof of ignorance of what money and goods really represent and if Christmas shopping frequently is indiscriminate spending, then... what can validly be deduced from this, if anything?
Give reasons for your conclusion's validity or invalidity.


3) Analyse the following syllogistic structure by the aid of Venn's diagrams and answer whether a valid conclusion can be obtained from it and whether you consider the syllogism logically valid;-
All S are M
and Some M are P
then Some S are P.


SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES IN VALID INFERENCE


1) One can validly conclude that 'a movie actor was a male'' - which also happens to be true. The reverse is true but invalid (i.e. that 'a male was a movie actor'). The validity of this syllogism can be demonstrated by abstracting the logical form of the argument and showing the necessary relationship between the individuals and classes involved as follows:-
The logical form of the argument is the syllogism:-

If all M was S
and P was M
then P was S
(but not S was P)

this is satisfied by the diagram:-

 

2) The argument is:- If Christmas shopping frequently is indiscriminate spending and indiscriminate spending is a proof of ignorance of what money and goods really represent then Christmas shopping frequently is proof of ignorance of what money and goods really represent The logical form is valid as follows:-

If S is M
and M is P
then S is P

this is satisfied by the diagram:-


If S is M
and M is P
then S is P this is satisfied by the diagram:- If the premises are true, then the truth of the conclusion follows with necessity. However one interprets the first premise, it seems likely to be true, the only problem possibly being the word 'frequently'. Whether the second premise is true will depend upon how it is interpreted, and it is open to a variety of interpretations. Therefore the truth of the conclusion must remain in doubt, despite its logical validity.


3)
The logical form is invalid. This can be demonstrated by showing that some of the class of M can contain two distinct and separate sub-classes S and P as follows:-


Both the above diagrams show how S and P can exclude each other, while the following shows how it is possible but not necessary for 'some S to be P'.